Howard Gardner and the theory of multiple intelligences (Reframing the Mind)
Reframing the Mind
Howard Gardner and
the theory of multiple intelligences
http://educationnext.org/reframing-the-mind/
SUMMER 2004 / VOL. 4, NO. 3
Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple
Intelligences
(Basic Books, 1983)
(Basic Books, 1983)
Multiple Intelligences: The Theory into Practice
(Basic Books, 1993)
(Basic Books, 1993)
Intelligence Reframed: Multiple Intelligences for
the 21st Century
(Basic Books, 1999)
(Basic Books, 1999)
By Howard
Gardner
Checked
by Daniel T. Willingham
What
would you think if your child came home from school and reported that the
language-arts lesson of the day included using twigs and leaves to spell words?
The typical parent might react with curiosity tinged with suspicion: Is working
with twigs and leaves supposed to help my child learn to spell? Yes, according
to Thomas Armstrong, author of Multiple Intelligences in the Classroom,
especially if your child is high in “naturalist” intelligence–one of eight
distinct intelligences that Harvard University scholar Howard Gardner claims to
have identified. However, if your child possesses a high degree of what Gardner
terms “bodily-kinesthetic” intelligence, Armstrong suggests associating
movement with spelling. For example, a teacher might try to connect sitting
with consonants and standing with vowels.
Armstrong
is far from alone in placing faith in Gardner’s theory of “multiple
intelligences.” Gardner’s ideas have been a significant force in education for
the past 20 years–significant enough that they bear close study. How does the
scientific community regard the theory of multiple intelligences, and what
impact should the theory have on education?
Central
Claims
Gardner
first proposed his theory in 1983. Since then, it has undergone incremental but
not fundamental change, including the addition of one intelligence (bringing
the total to eight), the rejection of others, and consideration of the theory’s
applications. The theory rests on three core claims:
• Gardner
says that most psychometricians, those who devise and interpret tests as a way
of probing the nature of intelligence, conceive of intelligence as unitary. In Intelligence
Reframed, Gardner’s most recent restatement of his general theory, he
writes, “In the ongoing debate among psychologists about this issue, the
psychometric majority favors a general intelligence perspective.”
This is
not an accurate characterization of the position taken by most
psychometricians. As will be shown, the vast majority regard intelligence not
as a single unified entity, but as a multifaceted phenomenon with a
hierarchical structure.
• There
are multiple, independent intelligences. There are three
parts to this claim, and it is important to appreciate all three. First,
Gardner offers a new definition of intelligence, describing it as
“a biopsychological potential to process information that can be activated in a
cultural setting to solve problems or create products that are of value in a
culture.” Previous definitions were limited to cognition or thought; one was intelligent
to the extent that one could solve problems and adapt effectively to one’s
environment using thinking skills. Gardner self-consciously broadens the
definition to include effective use of the body and thinking skills relevant to
the social world. He also extends the functionality of intelligence to include
the crafting of useful products, not just the solving of problems. Second,
Gardner claims to have identified some (but not all) of the several types of
intelligence, which I describe below. Third, he claims that these multiple
intelligences operate independently of one another.
• The
multiple intelligences theory has applications to education. Gardner
has been careful to say that he has proposed a scientific theory that should
not be mistaken for a prescription for schooling. He makes clear that the
educational implications of children’s possessing multiple intelligences can
and should be drawn, but he believes that many possible curricula and methods
could be consistent with the theory. The sole general implication he supports
is that children’s minds are different, and an education system should take
account of those differences, a point developed in diverse ways by his many
followers.
One
Intelligence or Many?
Let’s
evaluate each of Gardner’s claims in turn, beginning with how psychometricians
view intelligence. In the early 20th century, many psychometricians did in fact
think of intelligence as a unitary trait, just as Gardner now claims. The
thinking at that time was articulated by Charles Spearman, who suggested that a
single factor (he called it g, for general) underlay
all intelligent behavior. If you had a lot of g, you were
smart; if you didn’t, you weren’t. However, by the 1930s some researchers
(notably Louis L. Thurstone) were already arguing for a multifaceted view of
intelligence. One might be intelligent in the use of words, for example, but
unintelligent mathematically. From the 1950s on, many psychometricians proposed
hierarchical models, which may be thought of as a mixture of the single-factor
and multiple-factor models. Except for a few holdouts, most psychologists now
favor the hierarchical model.
How can
one use data from tests of cognitive ability to evaluate the number of
intelligences? A straightforward approach entails administering a number of
separate tests thought to rely on different hypothesized intelligences. Suppose
tests 1 and 2 are different tests of verbal ability (for example, vocabulary
and spelling), and tests 3 and 4 are different tests of mathematical ability. If
there is one intelligence, g, then g should
support performance on all four tests, as shown in diagram A of Figure 1 (this
page). A high score on test 1 would indicate that the test-taker is high in g, and
he or she should perform well on all of the other tests.
Suppose,
however, that there are two intelligences–one verbal and one mathematical, as
shown in diagram B of Figure 1. In that case, a high score on test 1 would
predict a high score on test 2, but would tell us nothing about the
individual’s performance on the math tests, 3 and 4. Performance on those tests
would depend on mathematical intelligence, which is separate and independent of
verbal intelligence.
The data
support neither of these views. To continue with our hypothetical example, the
data show that all of the test scores, 1 through 4, are somewhat related to one
another, which is consistent with the existence of g. But scores
from tests of math ability are more related to one another than they are to
verbal scores; the same goes for verbal scores. A hierarchical model, shown in
diagram C of Figure 1, fits this pattern. In this model, g influences
both mathematical and verbal cognitive processes, so performance on math and
verbal tests will be somewhat related. But mathematical competence is supported
not just by g, but by the efficacy of a mathematical
intelligence that is separate and independent of a verbal intelligence. That’s
why math scores are more related to each other than they are to verbal scores.
It also explains how it is possible for someone to be quite good in math, but
just mediocre verbally. This logic applies not only to the restricted example
used here (math and verbal) but also to a broad spectrum of tests of
intellectual ability.
The
hierarchical view of intelligence received a strong boost from a landmark
review of the published data collected over the course of 60 years from some
130,000 people around the world. That massive review, performed by the late
University of North Carolina scholar John Carroll, concluded that the
hierarchical view best fits the data. Researchers still debate the exact
organization of the hierarchy, but there is a general consensus around the
hierarchical view of intelligence. Thus Gardner’s first claim–that most
psychometricians believe that intelligence is unitary–is inaccurate.
What Are
the Intelligences?
Gardner’s
second claim is that individuals possess at least eight independent types of
intelligence. The following list includes a definition of each along with
examples Gardner has provided of professions that draw heavily on that
particular intelligence.
• Linguistic: facility
with verbal materials (writer, attorney).
• Logico-mathematical: the
ability to use logical methods and to solve mathematical problems
(mathematician, scientist).
• Spatial: the
ability to use and manipulate space (sculptor, architect).
• Musical: the
ability to create, perform, and appreciate music (performer, composer).
• Bodily-kinesthetic: the
ability to use one’s body (athlete, dancer).
• Interpersonal: the
ability to understand others’ needs, intentions, and motivations (salesperson,
politician).
• Intrapersonal: the
ability to understand one’s own motivations and emotions (novelist, therapist
with self-insight).
• Naturalist: the
ability to recognize, identify, and classify flora and fauna or other classes
of objects (naturalist, cook).
Gardner
claims that everyone has all eight intelligences to some degree, but each
individual has his or her own pattern of stronger and weaker intelligences.
Gardner also argues that most tasks require more than one intelligence working
together. For example, the conductor of a symphony obviously uses musical
intelligence, but also must use interpersonal intelligence as a group leader
and bodily-kinesthetic intelligence to move in a way that is informative to the
orchestra. The claim of separate and independent intelligences is, of course,
central to Gardner’s theory. How do we know that these intelligences are
independent?
It is
important to bear in mind that the hierarchical model described in the previous
section is not a theory, but a pattern of data. It is a description
of how test scores are correlated. A theory of intelligence must be consistent
with these data; the pattern of data is not itself a theory. For example, the
data do not tell us what g is or how it works. The data tell
us only that there is some factor that contributes to many
intellectual tasks, and if your theory does not include such a factor, it is
inconsistent with existing data. Gardner’s theory has that problem.
Setting g aside,
the claim of independence among the eight intelligences is also a problem. Data
collected over the past 100 years consistently show that performances on
intellectual tasks are correlated. Even if Gardner’s theory did not include
some general factor, it should at least provide a way to account for this
correlation. The theory did not, and it was widely criticized for this failure.
In some later writings, Gardner has said that he questions the explanatory
power of g, not whether it exists–in other words, he doubts whether g makes
much of a contribution to abilities Gardner deems important. He has also
deemphasized the importance in his theory of whether the intelligences are
truly independent.
Let’s
allow, then, that the intelligences Gardner has identified are not independent,
but that there are a number of distinguishable (but correlated) intellectual
capabilities in addition to g. Has Gardner done a good job of
cataloguing them? It is instructive to examine the criteria by which Gardner
determines whether an ability is an intelligence. The criteria are shown in the
table on page 22.
Gardner’s
eight criteria appear to be quite rigorous: the psychometric criterion
described in the previous section and seven others that span different domains
of investigation. But Gardner weakens them by demanding that only a majority be
satisfied, and some are rather easy to satisfy. The psychometric criterion is
the most rigorous of the eight, but Gardner has largely ignored it. The
remaining criteria are so weak that they cannot restrain a researcher with a
zest for discovering new intelligences.
For
instance, a humor intelligence and a memory
intelligence certainly meet a majority of the criteria. Humor and
memory can be used to solve problems and create valued products in many
cultures and so meet Gardner’s definition of intelligence. Both can
be isolated by brain damage, each has a distinct developmental history, and
there is evidence for the psychological separability of each. Some individuals
show exceptional memory or sense of humor but no other remarkable mental
abilities. The evolutionary plausibility of each intelligence is easy to defend
as well. Humor would certainly be adaptive in a social species such as ours,
and the adaptive nature of memory should be self-evident.
By these
criteria I am also prepared to defend an olfactory intelligence and
a spelling intelligence and to subdivide Gardner’s spatial
intelligence into near-space intelligence and far-space
intelligence, thus bringing the total number of intelligences to 13.
(Gardner, for reasons that are not clear to me, excludes sensory systems as
potential intelligences, but not action systems such as bodily-kinesthetic.)
The issue
of criteria by which new intelligences are posited is crucial, and it is in the
selection of criteria that Gardner has made a fundamental mistake. Gardner’s
criteria make sense if one assumes extreme modularity in the mind, meaning that
the mind is a confederation of largely independent, self-sufficient processes.
Gardner argues that neuroscience bears out this assumption, but that is an
oversimplification.
For
example, suppose that mathematical and spatial intelligence have the structure
depicted in Figure 2, where each letter represents a cognitive process.
Mathematical reasoning requires the cognitive processes A through E. Spatial
reasoning requires the processes B through F. Are math and spatial reasoning
separate?
Most
people would agree that they are not identical, but they are largely
overlapping and don’t merit being called separate. By Gardner’s criteria,
however, they likely would be. If we assume that each process (A through F) is
localized in a different part of the brain, then if the part of the brain
supporting process A were damaged, math ability would be compromised, but
spatial ability would not, so the brain criterion would be met. If process A or
process F had a different developmental progression than the others, the
developmental criterion would be met. If A and F differ in their need for
attentional resources, the experimental psychological criterion would be met.
The criteria that Gardner mentions can be useful, but they do not signal necessarily separate
systems. In fact, the one criterion that Gardner has routinely ignored–the
psychometric–is the one best suited to the question posed: Are cognitive
processes underlying a putative intelligence independent of other cognitive
processes?
Gardner’s
second claim–that he has described multiple, independent varieties of
intelligence–is not true. Intellectual abilities are correlated, not
independent. Distinguishable abilities do exist, but Gardner’s description of
them is not well supported.
Should
Theory Become Practice?
For the
educator this debate may be, as Shakespeare wrote, sound and fury, signifying
nothing. What matters is whether and how the theory inspires changes in
teaching methods or curriculum. The extent to which multiple intelligence ideas
are applied is difficult to determine because few hard data exist to describe
what teachers actually do in the classroom. Even statements of schools’
missions are of limited usefulness, although dozens of schools claim to center
their curriculum on the theory. An administrator might insert multiple
intelligences language in an effort to seem progressive. Or an administrator’s
enthusiasm may be sincere, but if the teachers are not supportive, the
classroom impact will be minimal.
We are
left with indirect measures. Textbooks for teachers in training generally offer
extensive coverage of the theory, with little or no criticism. Furthermore, the
ready availability of multiple intelligences classroom materials (books, lesson
plans, and activities) leaves the impression that there is a market for such
materials. The applications they suggest generally fall into two broad
categories: curricular expansion and pedagogical stratagem.
Curriculum
expansion suggests that schools should appeal to all of the intelligences. Some
educators have called for a more inclusive approach that does not glorify any
one of the intelligences at the expense of the others. The theory has also been
viewed as providing a pedagogical stratagem–namely, to teach content by tapping
all of the intelligences. For example, to help students learn punctuation, a
teacher might have them form punctuation marks with their bodies
(bodily-kinesthetic intelligence), assign an animal sound to each punctuation
mark (naturalist intelligence), and sort sentences according to the required
punctuation (logical-mathematical intelligence). The motive may be that
students will most enjoy or appreciate the material when it is embedded in an
intelligence that is their strength. In this sense, intelligences may be
translatable. The student who is linguistically weak but musically strong may
improve his spelling through a musical presentation.
Gardner
has criticized both ideas. Regarding curriculum, Gardner argues that the goals
of education should be set independently of the multiple intelligences theory,
and the theory should be used to help reach those goals. In other words, he
does not believe that status as an “intelligence” necessarily means that that
intelligence should be schooled. This objection is doubly true if you doubt
that Gardner has categorized the intelligences correctly.
On the
subject of pedagogy, Gardner sees no benefit in attempting to teach all
subjects using all of the intelligences. He also expresses concern that some
educators have a shallow understanding of what it takes to really engage an
intelligence. Gardner writes, “It may well be easier to remember a list if one
sings it (or dances to it). However, these uses of the ‘materials’ of an
intelligence are essentially trivial. What is not trivial is the capacity to
think musically.” It is therefore surprising that Gardner wrote the preface for
Thomas Armstrong’s book, Multiple Intelligences in the Classroom,
which includes many such trivial ideas, such as singing spellings and spelling
with leaves and twigs, as mentioned earlier. In the preface Gardner says that
Armstrong provides “a reliable and readable account of my work.” The
inconsistency in Gardner’s views is difficult to understand, but I believe he is
right in calling some applications trivial.
Gardner
also writes that intelligences are not fungible; the individual low in
logico-mathematical intelligence but high in musical intelligence cannot
somehow substitute the latter for the former and understand math through music.
An alternative presentation may serve as a helpful metaphor, but the musically
minded student must eventually use the appropriate representation to understand
math. Gardner is on solid ground here. There is no evidence that subject-matter
substitution is possible.
Gardner
offers his own ideas of how multiple intelligences theory might be applied to
education. Teachers should introduce a topic with different entry
points, each of which taps primarily one intelligence. For example, the narrational
entry point uses a story (and taps linguistic intelligence), whereas the
logical entry point encourages the use of deductive logic in first thinking
about a topic. Entry points are designed to intrigue the student via a
presentation in an intelligence that is a particular strength for him or her.
Gardner also believes that a thorough understanding of a topic is achieved only
through multiple representations using different intelligences. Hence
significant time must be invested to approach a topic from many different
perspectives, and topics should be important enough to merit close study.
How
effective are Gardner’s suggested applications? Again, hard data are scarce.
The most comprehensive study was a three-year examination of 41 schools that claim
to use multiple intelligences. It was conducted by Mindy Kornhaber, a long-time
Gardner collaborator. The results, unfortunately, are difficult to interpret.
They reported that standardized test scores increased in 78 percent of the
schools, but they failed to indicate whether the increase in each school was
statistically significant. If not, then we would expect scores to increase in
half the schools by chance. Moreover, there was no control group, and thus no
basis for comparison with other schools in their districts. Furthermore, there
is no way of knowing to what extent changes in the school are due to the
implementation of ideas of multiple intelligences rather than, for example, the
energizing thrill of adopting a new schoolwide program, new statewide
standards, or some other unknown factor.
What is
perhaps most surprising about Gardner’s view of education is that it is not
more surprising. Many experienced educators probably suspected that different
materials (songs, stories) engage different students and that sustained study
using different materials engenders deep knowledge.
Multiple
Talents
One may
wonder how educators got so confused by Gardner’s theory. Why do they believe
that intelligences are interchangeable or that all intelligences should be
taught? The answer is traceable to the same thing that made the theory so
successful: the naming of various abilities as intelligences.
Why,
indeed, are we referring to musical, athletic, and interpersonal skills as intelligences?
Gardner was certainly not the first psychologist to point out that humans have
these abilities. Great intelligence researchers–Cyril Burt, Raymond Cattell,
Louis Thurstone–discussed many human abilities, including aesthetic, athletic,
musical, and so on. The difference was that they called them talents or
abilities, whereas Gardner has renamed them intelligences. Gardner has pointed
out on several occasions that the success of his book turned, in part, on this
new label: “I am quite confident that if I had written a book called ‘Seven
Talents’ it would not have received the attention that Frames of
Mind received.” Educators who embraced the theory might well have been
indifferent to a theory outlining different talents–who didn’t know that some
kids are good musicians, some are good athletes, and they may not be the same
kids?
Gardner
protests that there is no reason to differentiate–he would say
aggrandize–linguistic and logico-mathematical intelligences by giving them a
different label; either label will do, but they should be the same. He has
written, “Call them all ‘talents’ if you wish; or call them all
‘intelligences.'” By this Gardner means that the mind has many processing
capabilities, of which those enabling linguistic, logical, and mathematical thought
are just three examples. There is no compelling reason to “honor” them with a
special name, in his view.
Gardner
has ignored, however, the connotation of the term intelligence,
which has led to confusion among his readers. The term intelligence has
always connoted the kind of thinking skills that make one successful in school,
perhaps because the first intelligence test was devised to predict likely
success in school; if it was important in school, it was on the intelligence
test. Readers made the natural assumption that Gardner’s new intelligences had
roughly the same meaning and so drew the conclusion that if humans have a type
of intelligence, then schools should teach it.
It is
also understandable that readers believed that some of the intelligences must
be at least partially interchangeable. No one would think that the musically
talented child would necessarily be good at math. But refer to the child as
possessing “high musical intelligence,” and it’s a short step to the upbeat
idea that the mathematics deficit can be circumvented by the intelligence in
another area–after all, both are intelligences.
In the
end, Gardner’s theory is simply not all that helpful. For scientists, the
theory of the mind is almost certainly incorrect. For educators, the daring
applications forwarded by others in Gardner’s name (and of which he apparently
disapproves) are unlikely to help students. Gardner’s applications are
relatively uncontroversial, although hard data on their effects are lacking.
The fact that the theory is an inaccurate description of the mind makes it
likely that the more closely an application draws on the theory, the less
likely the application is to be effective. All in all, educators would likely
do well to turn their time and attention elsewhere.
-Daniel
T. Willingham is a professor of psychology at the University of Virginia.
Σχόλια
Δημοσίευση σχολίου