The Theory of Multiple Intelligences
The
Theory of Multiple Intelligences
Katie
Davis, Harvard University
Joanna, Harvard University
Scott, Boston University
Howard, Harvard University
Please
address correspondence to:
Howard Gardner
Harvard Graduate School of Education
Larsen 201, Appian Way
Cambridge, MA
02138 (617) 496-4929
hgasst@pz.harvard.edu
2
PART
1: Background
The theory of multiple intelligences, developed by
psychologist Howard Gardner in the late 1970’s and early 1980’s, posits that
individuals possess eight or more relatively autonomous intelligences.
Individuals draw on these intelligences, individually and corporately, to
create products and solve problems that are relevant to the societies in which
they live (Gardner, 1983, 1993, 1999, 2006b, 2006c). The eight identified
intelligences include linguistic
intelligence, logical-mathematical intelligence, spatial intelligence, musical
intelligence, bodily-kinesthetic intelligence, naturalistic intelligence,
interpersonal intelligence, and intrapersonal intelligence (Gardner, 1999).
According to Gardner’s analysis, only two intelligences—linguistic and logical
mathematical—have been valued and tested for in modern secular schools; it is
useful to think of that language-logic combination as “academic” or “scholarly
intelligence”. In conceiving of intelligence as multiple rather than unitary in
nature, the theory of multiple intelligences, or (hereafter) MI theory,
represents a departure from traditional conceptions of intelligence first
formulated in the early twentieth century, measured today by IQ tests, and
studied in great detail by Piaget (1950,
1952) and other cognitively oriented psychologists.
As described elsewhere in this volume, French
psychologist Alfred Binet (1911;
Simon & Binet, 1916) designed the precursor to the modern-day intelligence
test in the early 1900’s in order to identify French school children in need of
special educational interventions. Binet’s scale, along with the
contemporaneous work of English psychologist Charles Spearman (1904, 1927) on
‘g’, served as the principal catalysts for conceiving of all forms of
intellectual activity as stemming from a unitary or general ability for
problem-solving (Perkins & Tishman, 2001). Within academic psychology,
Spearman’s theory of general intelligence (or ‘g’) remains the predominant
conception of intelligence (Brody, 2004; Deary et al, 2007; Jensen, 2008) and
the basis for more than 70 IQ tests in circulation (e.g. Stanford-Binet
Intelligence Scales Fifth Edition, 2003; Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scales
Third Edition, 2008). MI theory, in contrast, asserts that individuals who
demonstrate a particular aptitude in one intelligence will not necessarily
demonstrate a comparable aptitude in another intelligence (Gardner, 2006b). For
example, an individual may possess a profile of intelligences that is high in
spatial intelligence but moderate or low in interpersonal intelligence or vice
versa. This conception of intelligence as multiple rather than singular forms
the primary distinction between MI theory and the conception of intelligence
that dominates Western psychological theory and much of common discourse.
A second key distinction concerns the origins of
intelligence. While some contemporary scholars have asserted that intelligence
is influenced by environmental factors (Diamond & Hopson, 1998; Lucas,
Morley, & Cole, 1998; Neisser et al, 1996 Nisbet 2008), many proponents of
the concept of general intelligence conceive of intelligence as an innate trait
with which one is born and which one can therefore do little to change
(Eysenck, 1994; Herrnstein & Murray, 1994; Jensen, 1980, 1998). In
contrast, MI theory conceives of intelligence as a combination of heritable
potentials and skills that can be developed in diverse ways through relevant
experiences (Gardner, 1983). For example, one individual might be born with a
high intellectual potential in the bodily-kinesthetic sphere that allows him or
her to master the intricate steps of a ballet performance with relative ease.
For another individual, achieving similar expertise in the domain of ballet
requires many additional hours of study and practice. Both individuals are
capable of becoming strong performers—experts-- in a domain that draws on their
bodily-kinesthetic intelligence; however, the pathways along which they travel
in order to become strong performers may well differ quantitatively (in terms
of speed) and perhaps qualitatively (in terms of process).
MI theory is neither the sole challenger to
Spearman’s (1904, 1927) conception of general intelligence, nor the only theory
to conceive of intelligence as pluralistic. Among others, Thorndike (1920; Thorndike, Bregman, Cobb, & Woodyard, 1927)
conceived of intelligence as the sum of three parts: abstract intelligence,
mechanical intelligence, and social intelligence. Thurstone (1938, 1941) argued that intelligence could better be
understood as consisting of seven primary abilities. Guilford (1967; Guilford & Hoepfner, 1971) conceptualized
intelligence as consisting of four content categories; five operational
categories; and six product categories; he ultimately proposed 150 different
intellectual faculties. Sternberg
(1985, 1990) offered a triarchic theory of intelligence that identified
analytic, creative, and practical intelligences. Finally, Ceci (1990, 1996) has described multiple cognitive potentials that
allow for knowledge to be acquired and relationships between concepts and ideas
to be considered.
Gardner’s theory of multiple intelligences, however,
is perhaps the best known of these pluralistic theories. This notoriety is due,
in part, to the sources of evidence on which Gardner drew, and, in part, to its
enthusiastic embrace by the educational community (Armstrong, 1994; Kornhaber,
1994; Shearer, 2004). Many hundreds of schools across the globe have
incorporated MI principles into their mission, curriculum, and pedagogy; and
hundreds of books have been written (in numerous languages) on the relevance of
MI theory to educators and educational institutions (Chen, Moran, &
Gardner, 2009). In 2005, a 10-acre ‘science experience park’ opened in
Sonderberg, Denmark with more than 50 different exhibits through which
participants can explore their own profile of intelligences (Danfoss Universe,
2007). In what follows, we outline the major claims of this far-reaching theory
as well as some of the adjustments to the theory made over the past twenty-five
years.
It should be pointed out that Gardner’s
conceptualization of multiple intelligence does not belong exclusively to
Gardner; other scholars and practitioners have made numerous applications of
the principal tenets, sometimes with little regard to Gardner’s own claims. In
this chapter, however, we focus principally on MI theory and practices, as put
forth by Gardner. Gardner’s (1983, 1999) conception of intelligence as
pluralistic grew out of his observation that individuals who demonstrated
substantial talent in domains as diverse as chess, music, athletics, politics,
and entrepreneurship possessed capacities in these domains that should be accounted
for in conceptualizing intelligence. Accordingly, in developing MI theory and
its broader characterization of intelligence, Gardner did not focus on the
creation and interpretation of psychometric instruments. Rather, he drew upon
research findings from evolutionary biology, neuroscience, anthropology,
psychometrics and psychological studies of prodigies and savants. Through
synthesis of relevant research across these fields, Gardner established several
criteria for identification of a unique intelligence (see Table 1).
Table
1. Criteria for Identification of an Intelligence
|
Criteria for Identification of an
Intelligence
|
1
|
It should be
seen in relative isolation in prodigies, autistic savants, stroke victims or
other exceptional populations. In other words, certain individuals should
demonstrate particularly high or low levels of a particular capacity in
contrast to other capacities.
|
2
|
It should have
a distinct neural representation—that is, its neural structure and functioning
should be distinguishable from that of other major human faculties
|
3
|
It should have
a distinct developmental trajectory. That is, different intelligences should
develop at different rates and along paths which are distinctive.
|
4
|
It should have
some basis in evolutionary biology. In other words, an intelligence ought to
have a previous instantiation in primate or other species and putative
survival value.
|
5
|
It should be
susceptible to capture in symbol systems, of the sort used in formal or
informal education.
|
6
|
It should be
supported by evidence from psychometric tests of intelligence.
|
7
|
It should be
distinguishable from other intelligences through experimental psychological
tasks.
|
8
|
It should
demonstrate a core, information-processing system. That is, there should be
identifiable mental processes that handle information related to each
intelligence.
|
(Gardner
1983; Kornhaber, Fierros, & Veneema, 2004)
Drawing on these criteria, Gardner initially
identified seven intelligences. However, in the mid-1990’s, Gardner concluded
that an eighth intelligence, naturalistic intelligence, met the criteria for
identification as an intelligence as well (see Table 2). Naturalistic
intelligence allows individuals to identify and distinguish among products of
the natural world such as animals, plants, types of rocks, and weather patterns
(Gardner, 1999). Meteorologists, botanists, and zoologists are all professions
in which one would likely find individuals who demonstrate high levels of
naturalistic intelligence. In a world where this particular skill is less
important for survival than it was in earlier times, naturalistic capacities
are brought to bear in making consequential distinctions with respect to
manmade objects displayed in a consumer society.
Table
2.
Gardner’s
Eight Intelligences.
Frames of Mind (1983, 1993),
Intelligence Reframed (1999)
|
|
Intelligences
|
Description
|
Linguistic
|
An
ability to analyze information and create products involving oral and written
language such as speeches, books, and memos.
|
Logical
Mathematical
|
An
ability to develop equations and proofs, make calculations, and solve abstract
problems.
|
Spatial
|
An
ability to recognize and manipulate large-scale and fine-grained spatial
images.
|
Musical
|
An
ability to produce, remember, and make meaning of different patterns of
sound.
|
Naturalist
|
An
ability to identify and distinguish among different types of plants, animals,
and weather formations that are found in the natural world.
|
Bodily-Kinesthetic
|
Bodily-Kinesthetic
An ability to use one’s own body to create products or solve problems.
|
Interpersonal
|
An
ability to recognize and understand other people’s moods, desires,
motivations, and intentions
|
Intrapersonal
|
An
ability to recognize and understand his or her own moods, desires, motivations,
and intentions
|
The above descriptions of the eight intelligences
that comprise MI theory relied upon the domains or disciplines in which one
typically finds individuals who demonstrate high levels of each intelligence.
This is because we do not yet have psychometric or neuro-imaging techniques
that assess directly an individual’s capacity for a particular intelligence.
For example, no test has been devised to assess directly whether an individual
possesses a profile of intelligences high in spatial intelligence; however, one
might reasonably infer that an individual who demonstrates excellent
performance in the domain of architecture or sculpture or geometry possesses
high spatial intelligence. Likewise, excellence in the domains of ballet or orthopedic
surgery suggests the possession of high bodily-kinesthetic intelligence. It is
possible that in the future more direct methods of measuring intelligences may
be devised—for example, through evidence about neural structures or even
through genetic markers.
In the twenty-five year history of the theory,
numerous researchers have proposed additional intelligences that range from
moral intelligence to humor intelligence to cooking intelligence (Boss, 2005;
Goleman, 1995). Gardner (2006b) himself has speculated about an existential intelligence that reflects
an individual’s capacity for considering ‘big questions’ about life, death,
love, and being. Individuals with high levels of this hypothesized intelligence
might be likely to be found in philosophy departments, religious seminaries, or
the ateliers of artists. To date, however, naturalistic intelligence has been
the only definitive addition to the original set of seven intelligences. In
Gardner’s judgment, neither existential intelligence nor any of the other 8
proposed intelligences sufficiently meet the criteria for identification as a
unique intelligence (a discussion of the reliability of these criteria in
identifying candidate intelligences is offered in Part 2 of this chapter). In
future years, new proposed intelligences might be found to meet the criteria
for identification as a unique intelligence (Battro & Denham, 2007; Chen
& Gardner, 2005). Conversely, future research may reveal that existing
intelligences such as linguistic intelligence are more accurately conceived of
as several sub-intelligences. These inevitable adjustments and adaptations of
MI theory, however, are less important than the theory’s overarching principle:
namely, that intelligence is better conceived of as multiple and content-specific
rather than unitary and general.
In describing intelligence(s) as pluralistic, MI
theory conceives of individuals as possessing a profile of intelligences in
which they demonstrate varying levels of strengths and weakness for each of the
eight intelligences. It is a misstatement within the MI framework, then, to
characterize an individual as possessing “no” capacity for a particular
intelligence (Gardner, 1999). Individuals may certainly demonstrate low levels
of a particular intelligence, but, except in cases involving severe congenital
or acquired brain damage, all individuals possess the full range of
intelligences. It would be equally inaccurate within the MI framework, however,
to assert that everyone demonstrates superiority or giftedness in at least one
of the intelligences (Gardner, 1999). As a pluralistic theory, the fundamental
assertion of MI theory is that individuals do demonstrate variation in their
levels of strength and weakness across the intelligences. Unfortunately this
variation does not mean that every individual will necessarily demonstrate
superior aptitude in one or more of the intelligences.
After twenty
five years of reflection on the theory, Gardner accentuates two primary claims:
l) All individuals possess the full range of
intelligences—the intelligences are what define human beings, cognitively
speaking;
2) No two individuals, not even identical twins,
exhibit precisely the same profile of intellectual strengths and weaknesses.
These
constitute the principal scientific claims of the theory; educational or other
practical implications go beyond the scope of the theory, in a strict sense.
PART
2: Review of Issues and pseudo-issues spawned by the theory
During the years since its inception, MI theory has
drawn considerable attention, primarily from psychologists and educators. The
attention has come in many forms, from scholarly critiques regarding the
development, scope, and empirical basis of the theory, to educational curricula
that claim to develop children’s intelligences in an optimal way. This
attention has led to new developments in the theory and promising practical
applications in the classroom. Yet, several reviews and critiques of MI theory
reveal misunderstandings regarding its empirical foundation and theoretical
conception of human cognition. In this section, we use these misunderstandings
as a springboard for exploring the theory in greater depth, with the purpose of
illuminating its major claims and conceptual contours.
The foundation and province of MI
theory
Some critics of MI theory argue that it is not
grounded in empirical research and cannot, therefore, be proved or disproved on
the basis of new empirical findings (Waterhouse, 2006; White, 2006). In fact,
MI theory is based entirely on empirical findings. The intelligences were
identified on the basis of hundreds of empirical studies spanning multiple
disciplines (Gardner, 1983, 1993; Gardner & Moran, 2006). Noted, too, is
the relative lack of empirical studies specifically designed to test the theory
as a whole (Visser, Ashton, & Vernon, 2006). Like other broad theories,
such as evolution or plate tectonics, which synthesize experimental, observational,
and theoretical work, MI theory cannot be proved or disproved on the basis of a
single test or experiment. Rather, it gains or loses credibility as findings
accumulate over time. Indeed, subsequent findings have prompted ongoing review
and revisions of MI theory, such as the addition of new intelligences and the
conceptualization of intelligence profiles. Much of the empirical work
conducted since 1983 lends support to various aspects of the theory. For
instance, studies on children’s theory of mind and the identification of
pathologies that involve losing a sense of social judgment provide strong evidence
for a distinct interpersonal intelligence (Gardner, 1995; Feldman &
Gardner, 1988; Gardner, Feldman & Krechevsky, 1998a, 1998b, 1998c; Malkus,
Feldman, & Gardner, 1988; Ramos-Ford, Feldman, & Gardner, 1988).
Relatively few critiques of MI theory have addressed
the criteria used to identify and evaluate a candidate intelligence. This state
of affairs is somewhat unexpected, since the criteria serve as the theory’s
foundation. Moreover, by drawing on cross-disciplinary sources of evidence, the
criteria represent a pioneering effort to broaden the way in which human
intellectual capacities are identified and evaluated. White (2006) is one of
the few scholars to question this effort. He suggests that the selection and
application of the criteria is a subjective – and therefore flawed – process. A
psychologist with a different intellectual biography, he argues, would have
arrived at a different set of criteria and, consequently, a different set of
intelligences.
The professional training that preceded MI theory no
doubt played an important role in its formulation. We do not argue the fact of
this influence, simply its effect. MI theory is the product of several years
spent examining human cognition through several disciplinary lenses, including psychology, sociology, neurology,
biology, and anthropology, as well as the arts and humanities. The criteria
that emerged from this examination formed the basis of a systematic
investigation of candidate faculties. Thus, in contrast to White’s depiction of
an idiosyncratic process marked by one researcher’s intellectual
preoccupations, the identification and application of the criteria represent a
systematic and comprehensive approach to the study of human intelligence.
Moreover, any attempt to pluralize intelligence inevitably involves either an
agreed upon stopping point (an acceptance of the criterion as stated or an
infinite regress --what stimulated this criterion rather than another
criterion?). Nonetheless, White is correct that ultimately the ascertainment of
what is, or is not, a separate intelligence involves a synthesizing frame of
mind (Gardner, 2006a), if not a certain degree of subjectivity.
Many critiques of MI theory pay scant attention to
the criteria and focus instead on the level of analysis used to classify human
intellectual faculties. Some scholars argue that the eight intelligences are
not specific enough. Indeed, findings from neuroscience lend support to the
call for increased specificity in the classification of intellectual
capacities. As Gardner pointed out in the original publications (Gardner, 1983,
1993), it is likely that musical intelligence comprises several
sub-intelligences relating to various dimensions of music, such as rhythm,
harmony, melody, and timbre. An analogous comment can be stated for each of the
other intelligences. In fact, one test of MI theory would be whether the
sub-intelligences within each intelligence correlate more highly with each
other than they correlate with sub-intelligences within other intelligences.
Were the classification of intelligences expanded to include such specific
faculties, however, the number would quickly become unwieldy and virtually
untranslatable to educators. At the other extreme are those scholars who claim
that MI theory expands the definition of intelligence to such a degree that it
is no longer a useful construct. Gardner has argued elsewhere that a concept of
intelligence that is yoked to linguistic and logical-mathematical capacities is
too narrow and fails to capture the wide range of human intellectual
functioning (Gardner, 1995; 12 Gardner & Moran, 2006). MI theory seeks a
middle ground between an innumerable set of highly specific intelligences, on
the one hand, and a single, all-purpose intelligence, on the other.
The description of individuals in terms of several
relatively independent computational capacities would seem to put MI theory at
odds with ‘g’ (psychometricians’ term for general intelligence). Willingham
(2004) argues that a theory of intelligence that does not include ‘g’ is
inconsistent with existing psychometric data. These data, consisting typically
of correlations between scores on a series of oral questions or
paper-and-pencil instruments, do provide
considerable evidence for the existence of ‘g.’ They do not, however, provide
insight into the scope of ‘g,’ or its usefulness as a construct. Neither
Willingham nor other “geocentric” theorists have yet provided a satisfactory
definition for ‘g.’ One might argue that ‘g’ is merely the common factor that
underlies the set of tasks devised by psychologists in their attempt to predict
scholastic success. Perhaps ‘g’ measures speed or flexibility of response;
capacity to follow instructions; or motivation to succeed at an artificial,
decontextualized task. None of these possibilities necessarily places ‘g’ at
odds with MI theory—and indeed Gardner
has never denied the existence or utility of ‘g’ for certain analytic purposes.
The current perseveration on ‘g’ does, however, suggest a narrowness that fails
to capture adequately the broad range of human cognition. Just how much of
excellence across the range of intelligences reflects a current or future
version of ‘g’ is at present not known.
Delineating the boundaries of an
intelligence
It is sometimes challenging to draw clear distinctions
between intelligences and other human capacities (Gardner, 2006c). Indeed, even
when we have mapped out completely the neurological underpinnings of the human
mind, the drawing of these boundaries will probably continue to involve
considerable judgment. At the same time, the undergirding criteria and level of
analysis of MI theory can be usefully employed to draw a number of key
distinctions. For instance, since intelligences operate on specific content
(e.g.. language, music, the apprehension of other persons), they can be
separated from so-called “across the board” or ‘horizontal’ capacities like
attention, motivation, and cognitive style. Whereas these general capacities
are thought to apply across a range of situations, the ‘vertical’ intelligences
are used by individuals to make sense of specific content, information, or
objects in the world. Thus, while attention is required to engage in any type
of intellectual work and motivation is needed to sustain and enhance it,
attention and motivation remain separate from the operation of an intelligence.
Moreover, it is possible that an individual may be quite attentive and/or
motivated with respect to one kind of content, and much less so with respect to
other contents.
Similarly, an individual’s cognitive style
(sometimes referred to as a learning or working style) is not tied to specific
content in the same way as is an intelligence (Gardner, 1995). A cognitive
style putatively denotes the general manner in which an individual approaches
cognitive tasks. For instance, where one person may approach a range of
situations with careful deliberation, another person may respond more
intuitively. In contrast, the operation of an intelligence entails the
computation of specific content in the world (such as phonemes, numerical
patterns, or musical sounds). A closer look at individuals’ cognitive styles
may reveal content-specificity. For instance, a student who approaches a
chemistry experiment in a methodical and deliberative manner may be less
reflective when practicing the piano or writing an essay. By the same token,
individuals bring to bear different styles depending on the intelligence or
group of intelligences they are using. The key distinction is that one can
bring either a deliberative or intuitive style to the interpretation of a poem,
but there is no question that some degree of linguistic intelligence will be
needed.
Indeed, in an illuminating discussion of the
relation between style and intelligence, Silver and Strong (1997) suggest that
an introvert strong in linguistic intelligence might become a poet, while an
extrovert with comparable linguistic competence is more likely to become a
debater. This observation also highlights the fact that there is not a
one-to-one correspondence between specific types of content and the
intelligences. Writing a poem and engaging in a debate are two distinct
activities that each draw on linguistic intelligence. Moreover, it is not the
case that a skilled debater will necessarily be a successful poet. In addition
to using linguistic intelligence, a debater may employ logical-mathematical
intelligence to structure a coherent argument, whereas a poet may draw on
musical intelligence to compose a sonnet. Other factors besides intelligence,
such as motivation, personality, and will power, will likely prove influential,
as well.
Other putative general capacities, like memory and
critical thinking, may not be so general, either. For instance, we know that
individuals draw on different types of memory for different purposes. Episodic
memory enables us to remember particular events like a high school graduation
or wedding, whereas procedural memory allows us to recall how to drive a car or
knit a scarf. These different types of memory draw on different neural systems
of the brain. Neuropsychological evidence documents that memory for one type of
content, such as language, can be separated from memory for other types of
content, such as music, shapes, movement, and so on (Gardner, 2006b).
Similarly, the kind of critical thinking required to edit a book is certainly
different from the kind of critical thinking required to balance a budget, plan
a dinner party, transpose a piece of music, or resolve a domestic conflict.
The understanding that intelligences operate on
specific content can also help to distinguish them from sensory systems.
Whereas sensory systems are the means through which the brain receives
information from the outside world, the intelligences have been conceptualized
as computational systems that make sense of that information once it has been
received and irrespective of the means of reception. Thus, the senses and the
intelligences are independent systems. The type and quality of the information
received by a sensory system determines the intelligence, or set of
intelligences, employed, not the sensory system itself. Thus, linguistic
intelligence can operate equivalently on language that is perceived through
eye, ear, or touch. Even musical intelligence, which is most closely linked to
a specific sensory system (audition), may be fractionated into information that
can be obtained via diverse transducers (e.g. rhythm, timbre).
The distinction between an intelligence and a skill
is another common source of confusion. Unlike sensory systems, which precede
intellectual work, skills manifest as a product of such work. More
specifically, they are the cognitive performances that result from the
operation of one or more intelligences (Gardner & Moran, 2006). Within and
across cultures, the types of skills displayed by individuals vary widely, from
cartoon drawing to swimming, from writing computer code to navigating ships.
Skills act on the external world. As a result, they are shaped by the supports
and constraints of the environment. Thus, whether an individual’s bodily-kinesthetic
and spatial intelligences are put to use in swimming or marine navigation
depends on an individual’s access to a body of water, a willing instructor, and
time for practice. Living in a culture that values the ability to swim or sail
(or scuba dive or catch fish) is another influential factor.
Skills can be grouped according to the domain in
which they operate. A domain (a neutral term designed to encompass a
profession, discipline, or craft) is any type of organized activity in a society
in which individuals demonstrate varying levels of expertise. A list of domains
can readily be generated by considering the broad range of occupations in a
society, such as lawyer, journalist, dancer, or electrician. (In modern
society, the yellow pages serve as a convenient index of significant domains).
As such, a domain is a social construct that exists outside the individual, in
society; skills in that domain can be acquired through various routes. An
intelligence, on the other hand, is a biopsychological potential that all
individuals possess by virtue of being human.
Because some domains have the same name as certain
intelligences, they are often conflated. However, an individual can, and often
does, draw on several intelligences when performing in a given domain. A
successful musical performance, for example, does not simply depend on musical
intelligence; bodily-kinesthetic, spatial, and even interpersonal and
intrapersonal intelligences are likely at work, as well. By the same token,
fluent computation of an intelligence does not dictate choice of profession; a
person with high interpersonal intelligence might choose to enter teaching,
acting, public relations, sales, therapy, or the ministry.
Domains are continually being reshaped by the work
of creative individuals (Feldman, 1980). Newton changed the domain of physics
with his universal law of gravitation and laws of motion, and Einstein
re-conceptualized it again with his theory of relativity. Like intelligences,
creativity involves solving problems or fashioning products; however,
creativity requires doing so in a novel way. Yet, novelty in itself does not
constitute creativity. An individual who fashions a novel product may not
necessarily alter a domain. Sufficient mastery of a domain is required to
detect certain anomalies and formulate new techniques or ideas that resolve
these anomalies. Since it generally takes ten years, or several thousand hours,
to master a domain, and several more years to alter it (Hayes, 1989; Simon
& Chase, 1973), creativity requires concerted focus and dedication to one
domain. For this reason, a person rarely achieves high levels of creativity in
more than one domain. Moreover, individuals do not have the final word on their
creativity. According to Csikszentmihalyi (1996), creativity is a communal
judgment that is ultimately rendered by the gatekeepers and practitioners of
the domain; there is no statute of limitations as to when these judgments are
made.
In contrast, the intelligences are used daily across
a variety of domains. In one day, a person may use linguistic intelligence to
write a letter to a friend, read the assembly instructions for a piece of
furniture, and question the fairness of a government policy in a class debate.
In developing one or more intelligences to a high degree, individuals become
experts in a domain and are readily recognized as such. It may well be that
individuals who become experts exhibit a personality configuration and
motivational structure quite different from that displayed by creators
(Gardner, 1993). For example, creators are likely to take on risks and deal
easily with setbacks, while experts may be risk-averse and aim toward perfection
in well-developed spheres.
In delineating the boundaries of an intelligence,
Gardner hesitated to posit an executive function (a “central intelligences
agency”) that coordinates the relationships among the intelligences, or between
the intelligences and other human capacities (Gardner, 1983, 2006b). The first
problem one encounters when considering an executive function is the prospect
of infinite regression: who is in charge of the executive? Further, it is worth
noting that many human groups, whether artistic, athletic, or corporate, follow
a decentralized model of organization and perform effectively without an
executive whose role it is to coordinate and direct behavior. At the same time,
neuropsychological evidence suggests that particular executive functions, such
as self-regulation and planning, are controlled by mechanisms in the frontal
lobe. Instead of viewing such functions as constituting a separate entity that
oversees the intelligences and other human capacities, Gardner and Moran (2007)
argue that executive functions are likely one, clearly vital, emerging
component of intrapersonal intelligence. Defined as the capacity to discern and
use information about oneself, intrapersonal intelligence engenders a sense of
personal coherence in two ways: by providing understanding of oneself, or
selfawareness; and by regulating goal-directed behavior, or executive function.
Thus, executive function is that part of intrapersonal intelligence responsible
for planning and organizing actions in a deliberative and strategic way. Viewed
in this way, executive function does not form the apex of a hierarchical
structure, but rather constitutes one vital component of an essentially
decentralized process.
Assessing candidate intelligences
Over the years, there have been many calls for new
intelligences to be added to the original list of seven. Yet, as noted above,
in more than twenty five years, the list has only grown by one (and a possible
second). This relatively small expansion is partly due to Gardner’s
intellectual conservatism; mostly, however, it can be attributed to the failure
of candidate intelligences to meet sufficiently the criteria for inclusion. For
instance, some of the proposed intelligences are really general capacities that
do not operate on specific content. Posner’s (2004) “attention intelligence”
and Luhrmann’s (2006) “absorption intelligence” fall into this category.
Absorption is arguably one component of attention and both are prerequisites
for intellectual work. It is not evident how either one is tied to specific
content, information, or objects in the world. For this reason, attention and
absorption are perhaps more properly viewed as components of the sensory
systems that precede and facilitate the operation of any one of the
intelligences.
Artistic intelligence is another candidate
intelligence that is not tied to any specific content. Since each intelligence
can be used in an artistic or a non-artistic way, it does not make sense to
speak of a separate artistic intelligence. Linguistic intelligence is used by
both playwrights and lawyers, and spatial intelligence is used by sculptors and
building contractors. Musical intelligence may be used to compose a symphony,
to announce the arrival of horses onto a race track, or to soothe pain in the
dental chair. The decision to deploy an intelligence more or less artistically
is left to the individual. The culture in which he or she lives can also prove
consequential, as cultures vary in the degree to which they encourage and
support artistic expression.
Candidate intelligences raise additional
considerations. Scholars (including Gardner himself) have explored the
possibility of a moral intelligence (Boss, 1995; Gardner, 1997, 2006b).
Morality is clearly an important component of human society, but it is not
clear that it is felicitously described as an intelligence. MI theory is descriptive,
not normative. As computational capacities based in human biology and human
psychology, intelligences can be put to either moral or immoral uses in
society. Martin Luther King, Jr. used his linguistic intelligence to craft and
deliver inspiring speeches about the quest for civil rights through peaceful
means. In stark contrast, Slobodan Milosevic used his linguistic intelligence
to call for the subjugation and eventual extermination of entire groups of
people. The two men also deployed their interpersonal intelligences in distinct
ways. MI theory merely delineates the boundaries of biopsychological
capacities; the way in which one decides to use these capacities is a separate
matter.
A closer look at another oft-proposed
candidate—humor intelligence—underscores a second ploy. There is no need to add
a new intelligence when it can be explained through a combination of existing
intelligences. Thus, humor can be seen as a playful manipulation of our logical
capacity. Comedians draw on their logical-mathematical intelligence to turn the
logic of everyday experience on its head. They also employ their interpersonal
intelligence to “read” an audience and make decisions about the timing of
individual jokes and the overall direction of their act. In this way, it is
more appropriate to speak of comedians as exercising a particular blend of
logical-mathematical and interpersonal intelligences rather than as displaying
separate humor intelligence. In a similar manner, Battro and Denham (2007) make
an intriguing case for a digital intelligence, but it is not clear whether or
how digital intelligence can be untangled from logical-mathematical
intelligence (with a smidgeon of bodily-kinesthetic intelligence tacked on).
Cooking is another candidate intelligence that is
more properly viewed as an amalgam of existing intelligences. In preparing a
meal, for instance, one might draw on interpersonal intelligence to decide on a
menu that will please the guests; linguistic intelligence to read the recipe;
logical-mathematical intelligence to adjust the ingredient measurements for the
size of the party; and bodily-kinesthetic intelligence to dice the vegetables,
tenderize the meat, and whip the cream. The preparation of a fine meal may also
draw on the only full-fledged addition to the original list of intelligences:
naturalist intelligence. Cooks will draw on their naturalist intelligence to
distinguish among ingredients and perhaps tweak a recipe by combining
ingredients in an unexpectedly flavorful way. Of course, sensory systems are
important in cooking, but it is the operations performed upon the sensory
information that yields intelligent (or non intelligent!) outcomes.
PART 3: Scholarly Work in the wake
of MI theory
Since its inception the theory of multiple intelligences
has been a subject of scholarly inquiry and educational experimentation. We
here examine three major fronts: research, assessment, and educational
interventions.
Research
A notable point of departure is the problem of how
to decide which research is relevant to testing MI theory as it has been
described in these pages. Some research that is described in MI terms may be
irrelevant (e.g., informal and unvalidated questionnaires, assessments using
paper and pencil or multiple-choice tests alone), whereas research that does
not mention MI explicitly could be important (e.g., transfer and correlations
between competencies, aptitude-treatment interactions, parsimonious models of
cognitive neuroscience brain activation patterns, etc.). Other conceptions of intellect
have faced a similar challenge in psychology (Mayer & Caruso, 2008).
Cognitive Neuroscience and MI
Evidence for the several intelligences came
originally from the study of how mental faculties were associated or
dissociated as a consequence of damage to the brain, and especially to cortical
structures. With the surge in the types of neuroimaging tools in the recent
decades, far more specified inquiries relevant to MI are possible. Nowadays a
consensus obtains that there is not a
one-to-one correspondence between types of intelligence and areas of the
cortex. Nonetheless it is still germane to detail how the constructs
outlined by MI can relate to brain structure and function.
Until this point, most neuroimaging studies of
intellect have examined the brain correlates of general intelligence (IQ).
These studies have revealed that general intelligence is correlated with
activations in frontal regions (Duncan et al., 2000) as well as several other
brain regions (e.g., Jung & Haier, 2007), and with speed of neural
conduction (Gotgay et al., 2004). An analogous kind of study can be carried out
with respect to specific intelligences (cf. emotional intelligence as reviewed
by Mayer, Roberts & Barsade, 2008). Ultimately it would be desirable to
secure an atlas of the neural correlates of each of the intelligences, along
with indices of how they do or not operate in concert. Researchers should
remain open to the possibility that intelligences may have different neural
representations, in different cultures—the examples of linguistic intelligence
(speaking, reading, writing) comes to mind.
From a
neuropsychological point of view, the critical test for MI theory will be the
ways in which intellectual strengths map onto neural structures and
connections. It could be, as proponents of general intelligence claim, that
individuals with certain neural structures and connections will be outstanding
in all or at least, predictably, in some intelligences. Were this to be the
case, the neuropsychological underpinnings of MI theory would be challenged. It
could also be the case that individuals with intellectual strengths in a
particular area show similar brain profiles, and that those who exhibit
contrasting intellectual strengths show a contrasting set of neural profiles.
It might also be the case that certain neural structures (e.g. precociously
developing frontal lobes) or functions (speed of conduction) place one “at
promise” for intellectual precocity more generally, but that certain kinds of
experiences then cause specialization to emerge—in which case, a profile of
neurally-discrete intelligences will ultimately consolidate.
Similar lines of argument can unfold with respect to
the genetic basis of intelligence. To this point, those with very high or very
low IQs display distinct combinations of genes, though it is already clear that
there will not be a single gene, or even a small set of genes, that code for intellect.
What remains to be determined is whether those with quite distinctive
behavioral profiles (e.g. individuals who are highly musical, highly linguistic
and/or highly skilled in physical activities) exhibit distinctive genetic
clusters as well. Put vividly, can the Bach family or the Curie family or the
Polgar family be distinguished genetically from the general population and from
one another? Or, as with the neural argument just propounded, certain genetic
profiles may aid one to achieve expertise more quickly, but the particular area
of expertise will necessarily yield quite distinctive cognitive profiles in the
adult.
It is germane to inquire whether, should neural
evidence and genetic evidence favor the notion of a single general intelligence
and provide little evidence for biological markers of the specific
intelligences, MI theory will be disproved scientifically. A question will
still remain about how individuals end up possessing quite distinct profiles of
abilities and disabilities. Whether the answer to that question will lie in
studies drawn from genetics, neurology, psychology, sociology, anthropology, or
some combination thereof, remains to be determined.
MI Assessments
From the start, a distinctive hallmark of MI theory
has been its spurning of simple paper-and-pencil or “one shot” behavioral
measures. Instead, with respect to assessment, Gardner has called for multiple
measures of performance and ecologically valid testing environments and tasks.
This approach to MI has been actualized by a large initiative for children,
Project Spectrum.
Project Spectrum is an assessment system for young
children that features a classroom rich in opportunities to work with different
materials—in the manner of a well-stocked children’s museum (Gardner, et al,
1998a, 1998b, 1998c; Malkus et al 1988; Ramos-Ford, Feldman, & 24 Gardner,
1988; see also http://www.pz.harvard.edu/research/Spectrum.htm). The Spectrum
approach yields information based on meaningful activities that allow for a
demonstration of the strengths of the several intelligences. While validity is
not something that can be examined with preschoolers, Spectrum tasks have been
shown to demonstrate reliability (Gardner et al., 1998a, 1998b, 1998c).
Spectrum transcends traditional assessments such as
the IQ tests in several ways. First, it highlights components of thought (e.g.
musical competence, knowledge of other persons) that are not typically
considered indices of smartness (Gardner, 1993). Second, the assessment is
based on “hands on” activities that have proved to be engaging and meaningful
for preschool children drawn from a range of social backgrounds (Chen &
Gardner, 1997). Third, the initiative seeks to document approaches to learning
(working styles) as well as the distribution of strengths and weaknesses across
the several intelligences—the so called Spectrum Profile. (For a comprehensive
description of components and guidelines by domain for activities, see Adams
& Feldman, 1993; Krechevsky, 1998; Krechevsky & Gardner, 1990; for
observational guidelines see Chen and Gardner, 1997).
Empirical studies using the Project Spectrum
materials have been instructive and useful. In one study, researchers worked
with at-risk students in a local elementary school’s first grade (Chen &
Gardner, 1997). The majority of students (13/15) demonstrated identifiable
strengths based on assessments spanning many areas of performance including
visual arts, mechanical science, movement, music, social understanding,
mathematics, science and language (Chen & Gardner, 1997). Gardner (1993)
has described this approach as efforts to identify
how a student is smart as opposed to whether the student is smart.
Identifying such strengths has the potential to detach an at-risk or struggling
student from uni-dimensional labels and offer a more holistic formulation with
respect to student strengths and potentials.
Other empirical investigations have sought to
document the validity of MI claims. Visser et al. (2006) operationalized the 8
intelligences and selected two assessments for each. Further, the researchers
categorized the intelligences into purely cognitive (linguistic, spatial,
logicalmathematical, naturalistic, and interpersonal), motor
(bodily-kinesthetic), a combination of cognitive and personality (intrapersonal
and possibly interpersonal), and a combination of cognitive and sensory
(musical). Study results showed a strong loading on g, or general intelligence,
for intelligences categorized as cognitive as well as intercorrelations among
intelligences, suggesting that strong MI claims are not held up empirically.
The study findings stand in contrast to those
reported from Project Spectrum studies, as well as those put forth by other
investigators (e.g. Maker, Nielson, & Rogers, 1994). These contrasting
results may be attributed to the use of standard psychometric measures, as
opposed to the employment of broader (but less specific) tasks that aim for
ecological validity and that can be used routinely in the course of daily
school activities.
As a visit to any search engine will document, many
researchers and practitioners of an educational bent have developed
rough-and-ready measures of the several intelligences. The best known such effort is Branton Shearer’s Multiple intelligences
developmental assessment scale (MIDAS) (1999), which has been used as a
tool for measuring MI in many research projects (i.e., dissertations, Masters’
theses; see http://209.216.233.245/aerami/dissertations.php). Such measures
provide a snapshot of how individuals view their own intellectual profiles.
Such self descriptions do not, however, allow one to distinguish one’s own
preferences from one’s own computational abilities, nor is it clear that
individuals are necessarily competent to assess their areas of strength. (How
many persons consider themselves in the bottom half of the population with
respect to driving skill, or sense of humor?) Optimally, descriptions of a
person should come from several knowledgeable individuals, not just the person
him- or herself. And optimally, the measures should tap actual intellectual
strengths. Of the methods with which we are familiar, Project Spectrum comes
closest to meeting these desiderata.
With respect to assessment generally, Gardner and
colleagues (Chen & Gardner, 1997) have advocated several key points. As
reviewed earlier, an important starting point is the assumption that
intelligence may be pluralistic rather than a unitary entity. Another key point
is that the intelligences are shaped by cultural and educational influences; it
follows that measuring them in natural contexts is preferable, if the results
are to be ecologically valid. Recognizing the limitations of static assessment
is also important – while such assessment sessions may serve other purposes,
they do not fulfill the tenets of MI which calls for dynamic assessment to
accompany the use of intelligences in culturally-meaningful contexts.
Perhaps most
important, intelligences can never be observed in isolation; they can only be
manifest in the performance and tasks of skills that are available, and
optimally, valued in a cultural context. Hence the notion of a single measure
of an intelligence makes little sense. Rather, any intelligence—say
linguistic—ought to be observed in several contexts—speaking, reading, telling
a story, making an argument, learning a foreign language, etc. Taken together,
such diverse measures would converge on linguistic intelligence; one assumes
that what each task shares in common with the remaining tasks is reliance on
some facet of linguistic intelligence. In sum, MI assessment calls for multiple
measures for each intelligence and “intelligence-fair” materials that do not
rely on verbal or logical-mathematical skills. Gold standard MI assessments
should avoid several pitfalls and aim for several goals, summarized in Table 1.
Table
1. Assessment characteristics for the multiple intelligences and traditional counterparts
(Adapted
from Chen & Gardner, 1997)
|
|
Traditional
Assessments
|
MI
Assessments
|
Over-reliance
on linguistic and logical mathematical abilities and measures
|
Sample
the gamut of intelligences and domains
|
Deficit-focused
|
Identify
relative and absolute strengths
|
Minimal
intrinsic value to activity/tasks
|
Immediate
feedback to students; Meaningful for students; materials with which children
are familiar
|
Performance
captured in a single score
|
Scores
on a range of tasks, across several domains for each intelligence
|
Detached
from context
|
Ecological
validity; Present problems in the context of problem solving; Instructive for
teachers
|
Research on MI as an Educational
Intervention
We turn finally to studies of educational settings
that have developed methods based on the core ideas of MI theory. In the most
ambitious study to date, Kornhaber, Fierros, and Veenema (2004) compiled data
on the impact of MI across many educational settings using interview and
questionnaire data on educators’ perceived impact of MI. Featured were
interview data from 41 schools, which had been implementing MI-inspired
curricular practices for at least three years. Staff at four fifths of schools
associated improvements in standardized test scores with the implementation of
MI. Additionally, MI was also associated with improvements in student
discipline (54% of schools), parent participation (60% of schools), and
performances of students diagnosed with learning disabilities (78% of schools).
The researchers attributed the success of MI-based practices to six compass
point practices: attention to the school culture, readiness to use MI, use of
MI as a tool for improved work quality, collaborations, opportunities for choice,
and a role for the arts.
Investigations of MI in educational settings have
taken several forms, including descriptions of how the theory contributes to
education (e.g., Barrington, 2004), how MI can be applied in the curriculum
(e.g., Dias-Ward & Dias, 2004; Nolen, 2003; Ozdemir, Guneysu, &
Tekkaya, 2006; Wallach & Callahan, 1994), and how MI operates within or
across schools (e.g., Campbell & Campbell, 1999; Greenhawk, 1997; Hickey,
2004; Hoerr, 1992, 1994, 2004; Wagmeister & Shifrin, 2000). MI approaches
have been credited with better performance and retention of knowledge as
compared to a traditional approach (for science instruction for 4th graders)
(Ozdemir et al., 2006) and with understanding content in more complex ways
(Emig, 1997). Similarly, MI approaches in the curriculum have been credited
with giving teachers a framework for making instructional decisions (Ozdemir et
al., 2006). Teele, who has devised one of the principal MI self-administered
instruments, suggests that “intrinsic motivation, positive self-image, and a
sense of responsibility develop when students become stakeholders in the
educational process and accept responsibility for their own actions” (1996, p.
72).
PART 4: Conclusion: Looking ahead
In a number of ways, MI theory differs from other
psychological approaches to intelligence. Rather than proceeding from or
creating psychometric instruments, the theory emerged from an interdisciplinary
consideration of the range of human capacities and faculties. The theory has
garnered considerable attention, far more in educational circles than in the
corridors of standard psychological testing and experimentation. Consistent
with that emphasis, numerous educational experiments build on MI theory, and
many of them claim success. However, because MI theory does not dictate
specific educational practices, and because any educational intervention is
multi-faceted, it is not possible to attribute school success or failure
strictly to MI interventions. Direct experimental tests of the theory are
difficult to implement and so the status of the theory within academic
psychology remains indeterminate. The biological basis of the theory—its neural
and genetic correlates—should be clarified in the coming years. But in the
absence of consensually-agreed upon measures of the intelligences, either
individually or in conjunction with one another, its psychological validity
will continue to be elusive.
What does the future hold for MI theory? It seems
reasonable to expect that these ideas will continue to be of interest to
educators and other practitioners. Having initially catalyzed an interest in
elementary schools, particularly with respect to students with learning
problems, the theory has been picked up by schools of all sorts, as well as
museums and other institutions of informal learning. MI ideas are also invading
other occupational spheres, such as business, and have proved of special
interest to those charged with hiring, assembling teams, or placement of
personnel (Moran & Gardner, 2006).
Uses of MI ideas within and outside of formal
educational settings hold great promise. In particular, new digital media and
virtual realities offer numerous ways in which learners can master required
knowledge and skills. At one time, it may have seemed advisable or even
necessary to search for the ‘one best way’ to teach a topic. Now, at a time
when computers can deliver contents and processes in numerous ways, and when
learners can take increasing control of their own educational destinies, a plurality
of curricula, pedagogy, and assessments figures to become the norm.
Individualized education does not depend on the existence of MI theory; and yet
MI-inspired practices provide promising approaches for effective teaching and
learning (Birchfield et al., 2008). Moreover, as lifelong learning becomes more
important around the world, the prospects of developing, maintaining, and
enhancing the several intelligences gains urgency.
Initially, MI ideas were introduced in the United
States and the first MI-inspired experiments took place there. But over the
last two decades, MI ideas and practices have spread to numerous countries and
regions. There are both striking similarities and instructive differences in
the ways in which these regions implement MI ideas, formally and informally. An
initial survey appears in ‘Multiple Intelligences Around the World” (Chen,
Moran, & Gardner, 2009). In addition to chronicling numerous
implementations of MI theory in more than a dozen countries, this work also
provides a fascinating and original portrait of how “memes” about intelligence
take and spread in different educational soils.
Gardner has long maintained that MI cannot be an
educational goal in itself. Educational goals, value judgments, must emerge
from discussions and debates among responsible leaders and citizens. Once goals
have been laid out, the question then arises: How and in what ways, can MI
ideas aid in the achievement of these goals? To be sure, a tight answer to that
question can rarely be given. Nonetheless, over time it should certainly become
clearer which MI ideas, in combination with which goals, have pedagogical
effectiveness and which do not. Within Project Zero, the research group with
which Gardner has been associated since its inception in 1967, MI ideas have
proved particularly congenial with the goal of ‘education for deep understanding.’
(Gardner 1999, 2006b).
Whether or not explicitly recognized as such, MI
ideas are likely to endure within the worlds of education, business, and daily
practice—like the terms ‘emotional intelligence’ and ‘social intelligence’
(Goleman 1995, 2006), they are already becoming part of the conventional
wisdom. The status of MI theory within psychology, biology, and other social
and natural sciences remains to be determined. Attempts will be made to define
and redefine the set of intelligences, to evaluate the criteria by which they
are identified and measured, to consider their relationships to one another,
and their status vis-à-vis ‘general intelligence.’ In all probability, like
other attempts at intellectual synthesis, some facets will become accepted in
scholarship, while other parts will fade away or remain topics for debate. What
is most likely to last in MI theory is the set of criteria for what counts as an
intelligence and the idea of intelligence as being pluralistic, with links to
specific contents in the human and primate environments. The particular list of
intelligences and sub-intelligences will doubtless be reformulated as a result
of continuing studies in psychology, neuroscience, and genetics.
References
Adams,
M., & Feldman, D. H. (1993). Project Spectrum: A theory-based approach to
early education. In R. Pasnak & M. L. Howe (Eds.), Emerging themes in
cognitive development. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Armstrong,
T. (1994). Multiple intelligences in the classroom. Alexandria, VA: Association
for Supervision and Curriculum Development.
Barrington,
E. (2004). Teaching to student diversity in higher education: How multiple
intelligence theory can help. Teaching in Higher Education, 9, 421-434.
Battro,
A. M., & Denham, P. J. (2007). Hacia una inteligencia. Buenos Aires: Academia
Nacional de Educación.
Binet,
A., & Simon, T. (1911). A method of measuring the development of the
intelligence of young children. Lincoln, IL: Courier Company.
Binet,
A., & Simon T. (1916). The development of intelligence in children.
Baltimore: Williams Wilkins.
Birchfield,
D., Thornburg, H., Megowan-Romanowicz, C., Hatton, S., Mechtley, B., Dolgov,
I., Burleson, W. (2008). Embodiment, multimodality, and composition: Convergent
themes across HCI and education for mixed-reality learning environments.
Journal of Advances in Human-Computer Interaction, Volume 2008, Article ID
874563.
Boss,
J. (2005). The autonomy of moral intelligence. Educational Theory, 44 (4),
399-416.
Brody,
N. (2004).What cognitive intelligence is and what emotional intelligence is
not. Psychological Inquiry, 15 (3), p234-238.
Campbell,
L., & Campbell, B. (1999). Multiple intelligences and student achievement.
Alexandria, VA: ASCD.
Ceci,
S. J. (1990). On intelligence, more or less: A bioecological treatise on
intellectual development. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Ceci,
S. J. (1996). On Intelligence (rev. ed.). Cambridge, USA: Harvard University
Press.
Chen,
J.-Q., & Gardner, H. (1997). Assessment based on Multiple-Intelligences
Theory. In D. P. Flanagan & P. L. Harrison (Eds.), Contemporary
Intellectual Assessment: Theories, tests, and issues (Vol. 2, pp. 77-102). NY:
Guilford Press.
Chen,
Jie-Qi. & Gardner, H. (2005). Multiple Intelligences: Assessment based on
MultipleIntelligence Theory. In D. Flanagan and P. Harrison (Eds.) Contemporary
intellectual assessment: Theories, tests and issues. New York: Guilford Press.
Chen,
J., Moran, S., & Gardner, H. (2009). Multiple intelligences around the
world. New York: Jossey-Bass.
Csikszentmihalyi,
M. (1996). Creativity : Flow and the psychology of discovery and invention (1st
ed.). New York: HarperCollinsPublishers.
Danfoss
Universe. (2007). Retrieved July 1, 2007 from http://www.danfossuniverse.com.
Deary,
I., Strand, S., Smith, P., & Fernandes, C. (2007). Intelligence and
educational achievement. Intelligence, 35, 13-21.
Diamond,
M., and Hopson, J. (1998). Magic trees of the mind: How to nurture your child’s
intelligence, creativity, and healthy emotions from birth through adolescence.
New York: Dutton.
Dias
Ward, C., & Dias, M. J. (2004). Ladybugs across the curriculum. Science and
Children, 41(7), 40-44.
Emig,
V. B. (1997). A multiple intelligences inventory. Educational Leadership,
55(1), 47.
Eysenck,
H. (1994). Manual for the Eysenck personality questionnaire (EPQ-R Adult).
Educational Industrial Testing Service. Feldman, D. H. (1980). Beyond
universals in cognitive development. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex Pub. Corp.
Gardner,
H. (1983). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences. New York:
Basic Books.
Gardner,
H. (1993). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences (10 anniversary
ed.). New York, NY: Basic Books.
Gardner,
H. (1997). Is there a moral intelligence? In M. Runco (Ed.), The creativity
research handbook. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press.
Gardner,
H. (1999). The disciplined mind : What all students should understand. New
York: Simon & Schuster.
Gardner,
H. (2006a). Five minds for the future. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School
Press.
Gardner, H. (2006b). Multiple intelligences:
New horizons. New York: Basic Books.
Gardner,
H. (2006c). Replies to my critics. In J. A. Schaler (Ed.), Howard gardner under
fire: The rebel psychologist faces his critics (pp. 277-344). Chicago: Open
Court.
Gardner,
H. Feldman, D.H. & M. Krechevsky, M. (Gen. Eds.). (1998a). Project Zero
frameworks for early childhood education: Volume 1, Building on children's
strengths: The experience of Project Spectrum. Volume authors Chen, J-Q.,
Krechevsky, M., and Viens, J. with E. Isberg. New York: Teachers College Press.
Translated into Chinese, Italian, Spanish, and Portuguese.
Gardner,
H. Feldman, D.H. & Krechevsky, M. (Gen. Eds.). (1998b). Project Zero
frameworks for early childhood education: Volume 2, Project Spectrum early
learning activities. Volume author Chen, J-Q., with E. Isberg and M.
Krechevsky. New York: Teachers College Press. Translated into Chinese, Italian,
Spanish, and Portuguese.
Gardner,
H. Feldman, D.H. & Krechevsky, M. (Gen. Eds.). (1998c). Project Zero
frameworks for early childhood education: Volume 3, Project Spectrum preschool
assessment handbook. Volume author Krechevsky, M. New York: Teachers College
Press. Translated into Chinese, Italian, Spanish and Portuguese.
Gardner,
H., & Laskin, E. (1995). Leading minds: An anatomy of leadership. New York,
NY: BasicBooks.
Gardner,
H., & Moran, S. (2006). The science of multiple intelligences theory: A
response to Lynn Waterhouse. Educational Psychologist, 41(4), 227-232.
Gogtay,
N., Giedd, J. N., Lusk, L., Hayashi, K. M., Greenstein, D., Vaituzis, A. C., et
al. (2004). Dynamic mapping of human cortical development during childhood
through early adulthood. PNAS, 101(21), 8174-8179.
Goleman
D. 1995. Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.
Goleman,
D. (2006). Social intelligence: The new science of human relationships. New
York: Bantam Books.
Greenhawk,
J. (1997). Multiple intelligences meet standards. Educational Leadership,
55(1), 62- 64.
Guilford,
J. P. (1967). The nature of human intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Guilford,
J. P., & Hoepfner, R. (1971). The analysis of intelligence. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Haier,
R. J., & Jung, R. E. (2007). Beautiful minds (i.e., brains) and the neural
basis of intelligence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(02), 174-178.
Hayes,
J. R. (1989). Cognitive processes in creativity. In J. A. Glover, R. R.
Ronning, C. R. Reynolds, J. A. Glover, R. R. Ronning & C. R. Reynolds
(Eds.), Handbook of creativity. (pp. 135-145). New York, NY US: Plenum Press.
Herrnstein
R.J. & Murray C. (1994). The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure
in American Life. New York: Free Press.
Hoerr,
T. (2004). How MI Informs Teaching at New City School. Teachers College Record,
106(1), 40-48.
Hoerr,
T. R. (1992). How our school applied multiple intelligences theory. Educational
Leadership, 50(2), 67-68.
Hoerr,
T. R. (1994). How the New City School applies the multiple intelligences.
Educational Leadership, 52(3), 29-33.
Jensen,
A. R. (1980). Bias in mental testing. New York: Free Press.
Jensen,
A. R. (1998). The g factor: The science of mental ability. Westport, USA:
Praeger/Greenwoood.
Jensen,
A. (2008). Why is reaction time correlated with psychometric ‘g’? Current
Directions in Psychological Science, 2 (2), 53-56.
Kornhaber,
M. (1994) Multiple intelligences: Why and how schools use it. Unpublished
qualifying paper, Harvard Graduate School of Education.
Kornhaber,
M., Fierros, E., & Veenema, S. (2004). Multiple Intelligences: Best Ideas
from Research and Practice. Boston: Pearson Education Inc.
Krechevsky,
M. (1998). Project Spectrum preschool assessment handbook. New York: Teachers
College Press.
Krechevsky,
M., & Gardner, H. (1990). The emergence and nurturance of multiple
intelligences: The Project Spectrum approach. In M. J. Howe (Ed.), Encouraging
the development of exceptional skills and talents. Leicester, UK: British
Psychological Society.
Lucas, A., Morley, R., Cole, T. (1998).
Randomised trial of early diet in preterm babies and later intelligence
quotient. British Medical Journal, 317, 1481-1487.
Luhrmann,
T. M. (2006). On spirituality. In J. A. Schaler (Ed.), Howard gardner under
fire: The rebel psychologist faces his critics (pp. 115-142). Chicago: Open
Court.
Maker,
C. J., Nielson, A. B., & Rogers, J. A. (1994). Giftedness, diversity, and
problem-solving. Teaching Exceptional Children, 27(1), 4-19.
Malkus,
U. C., Feldman, D. H., & Gardner, H. (1988). Dimensions of mind in early
childhood. In A. D. Pellegrini, & A. D. Pellegrini (Eds.), Psychological
bases for early education. (pp. 25-38). Oxford England: John Wiley & Sons.
Mayer,
J. D., Roberts, R. D., & Barsade, S. G. (2008). Human Abilities: Emotional
Intelligence. Annual Review of Psychology, 59(1), 507-536.
Moran,
S., & Gardner, H. (2006). Multiple intelligences in the workplace. In H.
Gardner, Multiple intelligences: New horizons (pp. 213-232). New York: Basic Books.
Moran,
S. & Gardner, H. (2007). "Hill, skill, and will": Executive
function from a multipleintelligences perspective. In L. Meltzer (Ed.),
Executive function in education: From theory to practice (pp. 19-38). New York:
The Guilford Press.
Neisser,
U., Boodoo, G., Bouchard, T., Boykin, A. W., Brody, N., Ceci, S. J., Halpern,
D., Loehlin, J., Perloff, R., Sternberg, R. & Urbina, S. (1996)
Intelligence: Knowns and unknowns. American Psychologist 51, 77–101.
Nisbett,
R. E. (2009). Intelligence and how to get it: Why schools and cultures count.
New York: W W Norton & Co.
Nolen,
J. L. (2003). Multiple intelligences in the classroom. Educational Leadership,
124(1), 115-119.
Özdemir,
P., Güneysu, S., & Tekkaya, C. (2006). Enhancing learning through multiple
intelligences. Journal of Biological Education, 40(2), 74-78.
Perkins,
D. & Tishman, S. (2001). Dispositional aspects of intelligence. In J.
Collis, S. Messick, & U. Scheifele (Eds.). Intelligence and Personality:
Bridging the Gap in Theory and Measurement. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates Inc.
Piaget,
J. (1950). The psychology of intelligence. London: Routledge & Paul.
Piaget,
J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. New York: International
Universities Press.
Posner,
M. I. (2004). Neural systems and individual differences. Teachers College
Record, 106(1), 24-30.
Ramos-Ford,
V., Feldman, D. H., & Gardner, H. (1988). A new look at intelligence
through project spectrum. New Horizons for Learning, 8(3), 6-15.
Shearer,
B. (1999). Multiple intelligences developmental assessment scale. Kent, OH:
Multiple Intelligences Research and Consulting.
Shearer,
C.B. (2004). Using a multiple intelligences assessment to promote teacher
development and student achievement. Teachers College Record, 106(1), 147-162.
Silver,
H., & Strong, R. (1997). Integrating learning styles and multiple
intelligences. Educational Leadership, 55(1), 22.
Simon,
H. A., & Chase, W. (1973). Skill in chess. American Scientist, 61, 394-403.
Spearman,
Charles. (1904) General intelligence, objectively determined and measured.
American Journal of Psychology. 15, 201-293.
Spearman,
C. (1927). The abilities of man. London, UK: Macmillan.
Stanford-Binet
Intelligences Scales (SB5), Fifth Edition (2003). Riverside Publishing. http://www.riverpub.com/products/sb5/scoring.html
Sternberg,
R. J. (1985). Beyond IQ: A triarchic theory of human intelligence. New York, USA:
Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg,
R. J. (1990). Metaphors of mind. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.
Teele,
S. (1996). Redesigning the Educational System To Enable All Students To
Succeed. NASSP Bulletin, 80(583), 65-75.
Thorndike,
E (1920). A constant error in psychological ratings. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 4, 25-29.
Thorndike,
E., Bregman, E., Cobb, M., & Woodyard, E. (1927). The measurement of
intelligence. New York: Teachers College Bureau of Publications.
Thurstone,
L. (1938). Primary mental abilities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Thurstone,
L. L., & Thurstone, T. G. (1941). Factorial studies of intelligence. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Visser,
B. A., Ashton, M. C., & Vernon, P. A. (2006). Beyond g: Putting multiple
intelligences theory to the test. Intelligence, 34(5), 487-502.
Wagmeister,
J., & Shifrin, B. (2000). Thinking Differently, Learning Differently. Educational
Leadership, 58(3), 45.
Wallach,
C., & Callahan, S. (1994). The Ist grade plant museum. Educational
Leadership, 52(3), 32-34.
Waterhouse,
L. (2006). Multiple intelligences, the mozart effect, and emotional
intelligence: A critical review. Educational Psychologist, 41(4), 207-225.
Wechsler
Adult Intelligence Scales, Fourth Edition (2008). Pearson. http://www.pearsonassess.com
White,
J. (2006). Multiple invalidities. In J. A. Schaler (Ed.), Howard gardner under
fire: The rebel psychologist faces his critics (pp. 45-72). Chicago: Open
Court.
Willingham,
D. T. (2004). Reframing the mind. Education Next, 4(3), 19-24.
Σχόλια
Δημοσίευση σχολίου